Ta_Seti, a premier online African-centered discussion group!
King Nebhetep-ra Mentuhotep, Dynasty XL, 2060 - 2010 BC
(http://www.tulane.edu/lester/images/Ancient.World/Egypt/A57.gif)
To: athena-discuss@info.harpercollins.com From: "ERIC H. CLINE" [CLINE@xavier.xu.edu] Subject: Objects, Ideas, and Transmission Date: Wed, 8 May 1996 10:38:39 -0400 (EDT) On Tuesday, 7 May, Edward Kent said: "Writings are the stuff of elites, limited in space, time, and perspective -- so if we find stuff diffused, why not ideas as well?" In agreement and response, I proffer the following as food for further thought and discussion, again taken from my book _Sailing the Wine-Dark Sea_ (Oxford 1994): pp. 54-55: "In sum, although the evidence for Lambrou-Phillipson's `enclave colonies' at Boeotian Thebes and at Akrotiri on Thera is unconvincing, such hypotheses may have been on the right track. If the above criteria are applied to available and future archaeological data, it may yet prove possible to identify the presence of resident foreigners in the LBA Aegean. It is likely that individual Near Eastern craftsmen and perhaps diplomats will be (or have already been) identified at the larger cultural centers and citadels of the LBA Aegean, such as at Mycenae and Knossos. However, the vast majority of the Egyptian and Near Eastern personnel seen in the region are more likely to have been merchants and seafarers whose domiciles, whether permanent or temporary, were located in the port cities such as Tiryns and Kommos (cf. also Negbi 1988:357 and Morris 1990:58, 62). It is at such harbor sites, therefore, that we should look most carefully, and with the greatest hope of success, for evidence of resident foreigners in the LBA Aegean. "The idea of foreign seafarers, merchants, and craftsmen particularly in the port cities (and harbor taverns) of the LBA Aegean is, in fact, an attractive one, for we may well imagine these men as the simplest means of transmission for a variety of ideas and innovations. It is clear that there was much contact between the Aegean, Egypt and the Near East during the LBA, and transfers of ideas and innovations no doubt occurred. We might imagine that such transfers of ideas took place not only at upper levels of society, but also in the taverns and bars of the port cities in the Aegean and the Eastern Mediterranean. Where else would a sailor or crew member spend the long weeks waiting for the wind to shift to the proper quarter or waiting for a diplomatic mission to conclude its negotiations but in a tavern, swapping myths, legends and tall tales? It is easy to envision such mundane events taking place; resulting, occasionally, in dramatic cultural influences reaching Greece from Egypt and from elsewhere in the ancient Near East. Certainly, the notable parallels between certain Bronze Age Aegean epics and myths and those found in Bronze Age Syro-Palestine, Mesopotamia, Anatolia and Egypt (cf. Burkert 1987) may well be readily explained via the telling of such tales in the alehouses of the Aegean and Eastern Mediterranean. Transmission of Semitic `loan-words' and of Syro-Palestinian gentilics would also be readily engendered by such informal contacts. Such `low-level' transmissions may well have complemented the `high-level' or official contacts hypothesized by Morris (1989:42-46, 1990:58, 61-62; see also Burkert 1984 and West 1988)." Cheers, -- Eric H. Cline ---------------- To: athena-discuss@info.harpercollins.com From: "ERIC H. CLINE" [CLINE@xavier.xu.edu] Subject: Identification of "Foreigners" in the Aegean Date: Fri, 10 May 1996 18:01:22 -0400 (EDT) To the List: In a continuing (and thus far fruitless) effort to stimulate further discussion, I would like to ask the following: if there were indeed an Egyptian conquest of the Bronze Age Aegean (as per Bernal), or even a partial colonization by Egyptians or people from the Near East, or even simply some resettlement, how would one go about identifying the presence of Egyptians and other "foreigners" resident in the Bronze and Iron Age Aegean? As an initial point of departure, I submit the following food for thought (taken from _Sailing the Wine-Dark Sea_: pp. 52-54); comments and reactions on-list would be welcome and, indeed, are desired: "How then, acknowledging the possibility that they may have existed, can we recognize such resident foreigners in the archaeological record of the LBA Aegean? We should, as Branigan and Lambrou-Phillipson have suggested, set up criteria to identify such immigrants so that future scholars and excavators can have a secure framework from which to operate. Perhaps we can work backwards, from the known to the unknown, for resident immigrant craftsmen from the Eastern Mediterranean, or products from their Aegean workshops, have been identified at a number of 9th-7th century BC sites in the Aegean. These include Knossos, Afrati, the Idaean Cave, and possibly Kommos on Crete, and Athens, Lefkandi, Eleusis and Anavysos in Attica and Euboea on the Greek Mainland (Boardman 1980:37, 56-62, with references; Higgins 1980:96-101; Themelis 1983; Shaw 1989; Morris 1992:140-141, 155-161; Coldstream 1982:261-272, 1993:99-100; Sherratt and Sherratt 1993:365; but contra Muhly 1985c and Lembessi 1975). The criteria used to identify these Near Eastern immigrants in the Iron Age Aegean are simple: 1) votive goods; 2) burial goods; 3) burial techniques; and/or 4) religious architecture which demonstrate unmistakable Near Eastern origins or influences (cf. also Branigan 1981:25-27 and Schofield 1983:299 for similar criteria used to identify Minoan "Community Colonies" elsewhere in the Aegean, and further discussion in T.R. Smith 1987:156-158). "Strangely enough, given the occupations of the above Near Eastern immigrants, evidences of such resident emigres have rarely been identified in habitation or workshop areas in the Iron Age Aegean -- only their tombs and the objects produced in their workshops have been identified, such as goldwork found in 8th century BC contexts at Athens, Eleusis and Anavysos in Attica on the Greek Mainland (Boardman 1980:58; Higgins 1980:96-101; Coldstream 1982:266-267) and bronze shields evoking Near Eastern motifs given as votive offerings at the Idaean Cave in Crete (Dunbabin 1957:40-43; Boardman 1980:58-59; Shaw 1989:181; Morris 1992:152-154; Coldstream 1993:99). Thus, we should perhaps add several criteria to those mentioned above, so that we might identify additional evidence for such immigrants, if any exists. These might incorporate some of Lambrou-Phillipson's criteria (1987, 1990c), if used with the proper caution. Branigan's original criteria (1981, 1983; and Schofield 1983, 1984) will also be of value, if extracted from their original 'Minoano-centric' context. "It is essential to realize that any resident Syro-Palestinians [NB: or Egyptians, or Hittites, or ...] in the LBA Aegean would have been vastly outnumbered by the 'native' inhabitants, namely the Mycenaeans and Minoans. They will have been, quite literally, a 'minority' within the LBA Aegean. As such, therefore, we might turn to anthropology in seeking a means to identify such ethnic or cultural 'minority groups' residing in the LBA Aegean specifically as a result of an established trade network or diaspora (cf. Curtin 1984:1-14; T.R. Smith 1987:149-161; Sherratt and Sherratt 1991:356-357). As Harris (1988:413) says: `These groups...have distinctive life-styles that can be traced to the cultural traditions of another society...and...their members are conscious of their existence as a group set apart from the rest of the population.' "Such groups are usually identified by anthropologists via 'ethnic boundary markers,' which serve to distinguish their members from all other groups. These can entail differences in language, religion, physical appearance, or particular socio-cultural traits including clothing, architecture, personal adornment, food, technology, and general lifestyle. Combinations of such 'markers' are commonly used, since a single 'boundary marker' is seldom sufficient to allow conclusive identification (Weber 1961; Barth 1969; Cohen 1978:385-387; Reminick 1983:8-13; De Vos 1975; Schwartz 1975; Harris 1988:413; Peoples and Bailey 1991:375-376; Howard 1993:237). Most such 'markers' will, of course, not have survived a burial of 3500 years and will not be present in the archaeological record. Some, however, will still be extant, particularly the material remains left from the above socio-cultural traits -- namely architecture, objects of personal adornment, and artifacts resulting from new technology. "Anthropologists have noted that ethnic or cultural 'minority groups' frequently assimilate rapidly into the larger local community (Barth 1969; De Vos 1975; Reminick 1983:18-40; Peoples and Bailey 1991:376-377). If this occurred in the LBA Aegean, it will be extremely difficult to identify such 'enclave colonies' or 'minority groups,' as Schofield (1983:296) and Lambrou-Phillipson (1987) have pointed out (cf. also Harris 1988:416; Tournavitou 1990). Individual residents may not ever reveal their presence in the archaeological record; others may reveal themselves only in death -- via burial goods or burial customs. This is the case with the 9th century BC Near Eastern goldsmith and his family buried in the Teke tomb at Knossos, who were identified by the burial of two 'crocks of gold' as a foundation deposit just inside the entrance to the tomb -- a predominantly Eastern practice -- and by the nature and style of the goldwork found inside, which find their best parallels at Tell Halaf in Mesopotamia (Boardman 1967, 1980:57; Higgins 1980:107-111; Coldstream 1982:267-268, 1993:99-100; Shaw 1989:181; Morris 1992:157-158, 161 n. 55). We should note also the bronze bowl inscribed with a personal name in Phoenician letters found in another 9th century BC burial at Knossos (Boardman 1980:37, figure 6; Cross 1980:15-17; Coldstream 1982:271-272; Shaw 1989:181 and n. 64; Morris 1992:159; Sherratt and Sherratt 1993:365). "However, an entire 'enclave' of resident aliens will more than likely be apparent in some manner in the archaeological record, even if it is only in the textual evidence, as in the case for the Assyrian colony at Kultepe-Kanesh in Anatolia. Anthropologists have long noted that an ethnic or cultural 'minority group' will frequently live separately from, or separately within, the larger community -- either voluntarily or involuntarily (Barth 1969; Milosz 1975; Cohen 1978; Reminick 1983:8, 27-28; Curtin 1984:11-12; Harris 1988:416-417; Peoples and Bailey 1991:387; also Branigan 1981:26; T.R. Smith 1987:157). This is, in fact, the observable case at LBA Ugarit in Syro-Palestine, where most of the resident foreigners, who included Cypriots, Hittites, Cilicians, Egyptians, Canaanites, Assyrians, Ashdodians, and others, were relegated to one or two special districts, including the port area at Minet el-Beidha, where they lived under the supervision of the akil k ri "overseer of the merchant colony" (Astour 1965b:253, 1973:25, 1981:25; Rainey 1963:319; North 1973:126-127; Courtois 1974:107-108; Linder 1981:35-36). "Lambrou-Phillipson (1987, 1990c) is correct in suggesting that radical changes in technology can imply the arrival of foreigners (cf. also Boardman 1990; Knapp 1990c:124, 128). Moreover, although foreign goods, changes in burial procedures, or changes in secular and religious architecture by themselves are not necessarily indications of resident aliens, a combination of more than one of these factors found together in similar contexts at a single site is a good indication of their presence. Three instances from Iron Age Crete serve as prime examples. At Afrati (ancient Arkades), the early 7th century BC cemetery yielded clay objects which imitate North Syrian objects in other materials, as well as containing distinctive Near Eastern cremation burials, in which lidded urns were set on flat dishes, covered by inverted pots, and surrounded by a ring of stones -- the closest parallels for these burials are found in the Iron Age cemetery at Carchemish (Kurtz and Boardman 1971:174; Boardman 1980:60; Morris 1992:160-161; Coldstream 1993:100). At Kommos, a tripillar shrine inspired by Phoenician models was set up in Temple B during the 8th century BC, while more than 200 fragments of Phoenician pottery, mostly amphorae, were found in Temples A and B, in contexts dating from the 10th-8th centuries BC (Shaw 1989; Morris 1992:155; Sherratt and Sherratt 1993:365). In the Teke tomb at Knossos, as mentioned, the 'foundation deposit' indicates a Near Eastern style of burial, while the gold objects found inside and elsewhere show new gold-working techniques and methods (Boardman 1967). In all three of these situations, it is the combination of criteria which gives rise to the suspicion that resident, or semi-resident, foreigners were present at those Aegean sites. "Thus, we might be able to identify the existence of resident Syro-Palestinians, Egyptians, Italians or other Mediterranean peoples in the LBA Aegean if we look for situations where more than one of the following criteria are found together: 1. worked foreign goods deposited as votive offerings 2. worked foreign goods deposited as burial offerings 3. worked foreign goods (a substantial quantity) in a workshop or crafts area 4. local materials worked in a manner previously foreign to the area 5. foreign non-luxury (i.e. day-to-day) items in habitation or burial contexts 6. changes in burial techniques or architecture paralleled or inspired by foreign antecedents 7. changes in religious architecture paralleled or inspired by foreign antecedents 8. changes in secular architecture paralleled or inspired by foreign antecedents 9. changes in technology paralleled or inspired by foreign antecedents 10. textual evidence attesting to the presence of resident foreigners If there are any sites in the LBA Aegean where several of the above criteria appear in combination, we might be able to hypothesize the presence of resident foreigners in the Aegean during the second millennium BC. "The 38 Near Eastern cylinder seals at Boeotian Thebes are the most famous objects which have been cited as evidence for Syro-Palestinian colonists in the LBA Aegean. Such assertions were put forth soon after the discovery of these seals by scholars trying, among other things, to correlate these finds with the legends surrounding the Phoenician Kadmos (Culican 1966:54-55; Sasson 1966:135 n. 53; Astour 1967:387; Hemmerdinger 1967:232-240). They were repudiated almost immediately (Muhly 1970:37-38, 41, 61; Edwards 1979:131-137; cf. Morris 1990:58-60, 1992:104). Since the presence of these seals fulfills only one of the above criteria (no. 3: 'worked foreign goods [a substantial quantity] in a workshop or crafts area') and since there is no other convincing evidence for such an enclave of foreigners, there is currently no basis to hypothesize any resident Syro-Palestinians at Boeotian Thebes. As noted above, suggestions for the imported cylinder seals as the raw stock of a local Mycenaean artisan or as the prized collection of a Mycenaean noble are more convincing; even Porada's explanation (1981) of these seals as a gift from Tukulti-Ninurta I of Assyria to the Theban king seems more likely. "Possible evidence for a resident Syro-Palestinian in the LBA Aegean may be seen in the reuse of Tomb Rho in Grave Circle B at Mycenae, of LH IIA date. The tomb exhibits characteristics comparable to slightly-later graves at Ugarit in North Syria and at Enkomi in Cyprus (Mylonas 1966:106-107, 1983:56-57). Moreover, the reworked tomb originally contained a lapis lazuli scarab of possible Hyksos origin (152). Tomb Rho, like the above 9th century BC Teke tomb at Knossos, thus meets two of the above criteria: no. 2 ('worked foreign goods deposited as burial goods') and no. 6 ('changes in burial techniques or architecture paralleled or inspired by foreign antecedents'). However, it must be noted that the characteristics of Tomb Rho have now been shown to be as comparable to local Aegean tombs at Ayia Irini on Kea, Phylakopi on Melos and at Thorikos on the Greek Mainland as they are to the tombs at Ugarit and Enkomi (Dickinson 1977:64). Since none of these other Aegean graves contain Orientalia, it is likely that only architectural influences, rather than actual immigrants, from Syro-Palestine are reflected in these Aegean burials, including Tomb Rho. "Perhaps the most viable evidence for resident foreigners physically present in the LBA Aegean may be seen at Phylakopi, Tiryns, and elsewhere at Mycenae. First, Negbi (1988:341-345; cf. also Morris 1992:110-111) has amply documented that the architecture of the sanctuary at Phylakopi on Melos during the LH IIIC period, and perhaps during the LH IIIA and IIIB periods as well, is related and indebted to Levantine sacred architecture present in Canaan during the Middle and Late Bronze Ages. Moreover, there are numerous Orientalia found in and around the Phylakopi sanctuary, including two Canaanite 'Smiting God' statuettes (14-15), an Egyptian stone pendant (84), an Egyptian or Syro-Palestinian faience scarab (124), and a Near Eastern rhyton made of ostrich eggshell (950). Thus, at Phylakopi we meet two of the above criteria: no. 1 ('worked foreign goods deposited as votive offerings') and no. 7 ('changes in religious architecture paralleled or inspired by foreign antecedents'). Negbi (1988:357) is almost certainly correct in suggesting that: `the minor shrine of Phylakopi was reserved for foreign cult that was presumably practiced by Canaanite seafarers engaged in East Mediterranean trade.' "Second, Negbi (1988; followed and enlarged by Morris 1992:108-109) has pointed out that portions of the Cult Center at Mycenae may also have antecedents in Levantine sacred architecture. If true, then the Orientalia found in the Cult Center (69, 97, 100, 119-120) take on further importance, for the same two criteria for resident foreigners at Phylakopi would be present at Mycenae: no. 1 ('worked foreign goods deposited as votive offerings') and no. 7 ('changes in religious architecture paralleled or inspired by foreign antecedents'). Moreover, if the faience plaque of Amenhotep III (97) found in Room 31 of the Cult Center is of local Mycenaean manufacture (Cline 1990:210), then we would fulfill a third criteria -- no. 9 ('changes in technology paralleled or inspired by foreign antecedents') -- and would have evidence for at least one Egyptian craftsman resident at LBA Mycenae. "Third, at Tiryns the relatively large numbers of Cypriot non-luxury goods found only in LH IIIB contexts at this site -- nine terracotta wall brackets and three ceramic vessels (399-400, 632, 788-796) -- may imply the existence of resident foreigners. Furthermore, Hirschfeld (1990) has determined that a number of LH III vessels manufactured locally at Tiryns had Cypro-Minoan marks (at least 16 different signs) incised after firing but before they left the Greek Mainland; corresponding vessels with similar marks have been found on Cyprus itself. This may indicate a Mycenaean export trade aimed specifically at Cyprus, and the presence of individuals at Tiryns who were familiar with the Cypro-Minoan marking system (if not themselves Cypriote). Two of the above criteria may thus be fulfilled at Tiryns: no. 4 ('local materials worked in a manner previously foreign to the area;' e.g. incising with Cypro-Minoan marks) and no. 5 ('foreign non-luxury [i.e. day-to-day] items in habitation contexts'). While these may simply be indicative of reciprocal trade -- Mycenaean vessels for Cypriot wall brackets and pottery -- they might also be seen as tentative evidence for resident Cypriots at Tiryns. "The possible Syro-Palestinian personal names found in the Linear B texts (A-ra-da-jo, Pe-ri-ta, Tu-ri-jo, and po-ni-ki-jo) also may very well be an indication of the presence of individual Syro-Palestinians in the LBA Aegean. They are, however, unlikely to be evidence for entire 'enclave colonies.' Moreover, the extensive contact and trade between the LBA Aegean, Egypt and the Near East provide a ready explanation for the numbers of Semitic "loan-words" found in the Linear B texts (above), without resorting to the notion of colonies or conquest by Syro-Palestinians. These few words in the Linear B tablets are a far cry from the extensive textual documentation which should be present if entire 'enclave colonies' were in residence at Akrotiri, Thebes, Tiryns, Pylos, Knossos or Mycenae, although it is conceivable that such records have not yet been found or that they were kept on perishable materials such as papyrus. "In sum, although the evidence for Lambrou-Phillipson's 'enclave colonies' at Boeotian Thebes and at Akrotiri on Thera is unconvincing, such hypotheses may have been on the right track. If the above criteria are applied to available and future archaeological data, it may yet prove possible to identify the presence of resident foreigners in the LBA Aegean." Thoughts and reactions, anyone? Cheers, -- Eric H. Cline ------------------ To: athena-discuss@info.harpercollins.com From: "ERIC H. CLINE" Subject: Egyptian Objects in Greece Date: Tue, 7 May 1996 12:09:47 -0400 (EDT) In reply to Chuck Grimes' posting on Sunday, 5 May regarding Egyptian artifacts in Greece: Chuck, I am afraid that you are incorrect to state: "So where are the Egyptian artifacts in Greece? As far as I know there are none." There are, in fact, some 236 Egyptian objects found in Late Bronze Age contexts on the Greek mainland, Crete and the Cycladic islands. There are even more Egyptian objects found in later contexts in the Aegean area, e.g. during and after the so-called "Orientalizing" period during the first millennium BC. Allow me to take this opportunity to introduce some relevant hard data into this discussion by quoting from the chapter entitled "Egypt and the Late Bronze Age Aegean" in my recent book (_Sailing the Wine-Dark Sea: International Trade and the Late Bronze Age Aegean_; Oxford: Tempus Reparatum, 1994): p. 31-32: "Much of the archaeological evidence, namely the Mycenaean and Minoan pottery found in Egypt, is well known. These Mycenaean and Minoan goods, primarily ceramic vessels which will have originally contained wine, oil or perfume, are found throughout Egypt during the New Kingdom Period. Ongoing excavations continue to increase the number of these objects -- which now number more than 1800 vessels of various shapes and sizes (Bell, personal communication). Although LH/LM [Late Helladic/Late Minoan] I-II pottery is relatively scarce, such sherds have been found at nine sites, including Abusir, Memphis, Gurob, Kahun, Sedment, Abydos, Deir el Medina, Thebes and Armant (Vincentelli and Tiradritti 1986:327-334; Kemp and Merrillees 1980:226-245; Manning 1990:93). A new LM IA or IB sherd, which may prove useful for chronological studies, has recently been excavated at Kom Rabia (Memphis) in Egypt (Warren and Hankey 1989:138-146, esp. 139 [RAT 530.1301]). LH/LM III pottery as a whole appears to have been consistently imported throughout most of the 14th-12th centuries BC. Such pottery has been found at approximately thirty sites in Egypt, from Marsa Matruh on the northwest coast to Sesebi in the far south (MAP 2). It should be noted that the accumulating evidence clearly indicates that the importation of Mycenaean pottery was not unique to Akhenaten, his capital at Tell el Amarna, or the 'Amarna Period', as previously suspected. Rather, such pottery was in use over great areas of Egypt and was imported by a number of Pharaohs, from Amenhotep III to Ramses II (Redford 1983:482; Cline 1987:13-16). "The other half of the extant archaeological evidence, namely the Egyptian imports in the LBA Aegean, include transport amphorae, storage jars, jugs, bowls and vases in ceramic, stone, and glass, as well as scarabs and figurines of faience, frit and steatite. More than half of these are functional items rather than trinkets, imported consistently over the course of the Late Bronze Age. The perishable trade goods, including perhaps grain, textiles, and metals sent between the two areas (e.g. Barber 1991:311-357; Bernal 1991:482-489), must also be taken into account; although these goods have long since disappeared, they can be seen depicted in Egyptian tomb paintings and are occasionally mentioned in written texts. "The high points of contact between Egypt and the Late Bronze Age Aegean seem to be during the reigns of Thutmose III, Amenhotep III, Ramses II, and possibly Ramses III. In all, there are some 236 Egyptian objects found in good LH/LM I-IIIC contexts. Of these, 75 are on the Mainland, 120 are on Crete, 11 are on Rhodes, nine are on the Cycladic Islands, 16 are on the Ulu Burun (Kas) wreck, and five are on the Cape Gelidonya wreck. These do not include the objects found in contexts too broad for assignation to a specific period (i.e. LH I-III). It is interesting to note that the situation in the LH/LM III Aegean, with regard to the importation of Egyptian objects, has become completely reversed as a result of excavations in the past sixty years. For instance, in 1930 Pendlebury (1930a:84-85) listed only two Egyptian objects found in LM III contexts on Crete; there are now 53. "It is likely that direct commercial trade between the Aegean and Egypt began at least as early as the emergence of the Minoan palatial centers (cf. Phillips 1990). As mentioned, by the time of the LH/LM I-II periods in the Aegean, Egyptian objects comprise the vast majority of the Orientalia. There are 82 Egyptian objects in these contexts, compared to fewer than 25 objects from any other Near Eastern country (TABLE 3, FIGURE 2). Fully 67 of these 82 Egyptian objects (82%) are found on Crete, most in LM IB contexts (TABLE 2, FIGURE 1). Even these numbers are misleading, for many of the objects found outside Crete (e.g. a number in the Shaft Graves at Mycenae) appear to have reached their final destinations via Crete. Quite a few were reworked by the Minoans, being altered and readapted for Aegean purposes after their importation (Phillips 1989)." p. 32: "Tomb paintings and literary references in Egypt during this time provide further evidence for contacts with the Late Bronze Age Aegean (Vercoutter 1956; Strange 1980; Sakellarakis and Sakellarakis 1984; Wachsmann 1987; Laboury 1990). References to the LBA Aegean and to Aegean peoples are far more common in Egypt than in any other Near Eastern country. The term Kft(j)w, vocalized as Keftiu, is most likely the Egyptian name for the island of Crete and the Bronze Age Minoans (Vercoutter 1956:33-38, 116-122; contra Strange [1980], who attempted to equate the term with the island of Cyprus; and contra Morris 1992:102-103, who suggested that the term is a more general reference to all Aegean and even Levantine seafarers). The term Iww hryw-ib nw W3d-wr, translated as "the Isles in the Midst of the Great Green," is usually taken as a reference to the Cycladic islands of the Aegean, perhaps including Crete (Vercoutter 1956:125-127, 149-157; contra Vandersleyen 1985:44-46). The term Tj-n3-jj is to be read Tanaja (possibly vocalized as a variation of *Danaoi) and is most likely a specific reference to the land of the Mycenaeans, in the Late Bronze Age Peloponnese (Faure 1968:145-147). These three terms occur primarily during the 18th, 19th, and 20th Dynasties, but earlier references to Keftiu and to the Isles do occur; and later examples of all three terms can be found as well. A final term h3w-nbw.t (Hau-nebut), long thought to refer to Greeks and the Aegean, is more likely an allusion to areas in Syro-Palestine and has not been included in these discussions (cf. Vercoutter 1947, 1949; Vandersleyen 1971:140-174, 1988:78-80; Iversen 1987:54-59; Nibbi 1989:153-160; contra Bernal 1991:416-417, who argued for the re-establishment of this term as a reference to the Aegean). "In 1956 Vercoutter stated that references to Keftiu occur most frequently in Egyptian documents and tombs dating to the 15th century BC: a total of 16 times. He further stated (1956:114-115) that the following centuries saw a decrease in the occurrence of the term Keftiu: only two in the 14th century, three in the 13th, and one in the 12th century BC. However, matters have changed somewhat since Vercoutter's day. Some of the occurrences cited by him, in particular unlabelled scenes in tombs ostensibly depicting "Aegean" peoples, have been thrown out as unreliable for serious considerations. Other examples have been noted and added to the corpus over the past thirty years. "Thus, we now have the following instances in Egypt: Middle Kingdom Period: 1 Keftiu, 1 Isles, 0 Tanaja 17th-16th century: 3 Keftiu, 1 Isles, 0 Tanaja, 1 Generic 15th century: 8 Keftiu, 5 Isles, 1 Tanaja, 3 Generic 14th century: 6 Keftiu, 2 Isles, 3 Tanaja, 2 Generic 13th century: 6 Keftiu, 4 Isles, 2 Tanaja 12th century: 1 Keftiu, 9 Isles, 0 Tanaja These findings indicate a consistent pattern of contact between Egypt and the Aegean throughout the Late Bronze Age (see FIGURE 7)." p. 35: "In addition to the archaeological evidence in the Aegean, we also have textual evidence for this international trade. There are two textual references to Egypt and the Egyptians found in the Linear B texts in the Aegean. These appear only in the tablets found at Knossos: mi-sa-ra-jo = "Egyptian" and a3-ku-pi-ti-jo = "Memphite" or "Egyptian." The former term, mi-sa-ra-jo is interesting, as it apparently comes from the Semitic word for Egypt, Miraim, more commonly found in Akkadian and Ugaritic documents in Mesopotamia and Syro-Palestine. The latter term, a3-ku-pi-ti-jo, may also be derived from a Syro-Palestinian reference to Egypt, for an Ugaritic name for both Egypt and the city of Memphis was ikupta, which corresponds to the ikuptah of the Amarna letters and to t-k'-pt in Egyptian (see Virolleaud 1953:192). It is used in the Linear B tablet as the name of an individual who was in charge of a flock of 80 sheep at the Cretan site of su-ri-mo. The same name, again used for an individual, is also used later by Homer (Od.II.15). As Palaima (1991:280) states: `personal names derived from foreign toponyms also attest to overseas contacts at some stage prior to the dates of the tablets on which they are recorded.'" Discussants on this list might also be interested in the data originally presented by me in: "Of Shoes and Ships and Sealing Wax: International Trade and the Late Bronze Age Aegean," _Expedition_ 33/3 (1991) 46-54 (with M.J. Cline). [NB: written for a "lay" audience] "Contact and Trade or Colonization?: Egypt and the Aegean in the 14th - 13th Centuries B.C.," _Minos_ 25/26 (1990-91) 7-36. "Amenhotep III and the Aegean: A Reassessment of Egypto-Aegean Relations in the 14th Century BC," _Orientalia_ 56/1 (1987) 1-36. Cheers, -- Eric H. Cline ------------------- To: athena-discuss@info.harpercollins.com From: "Staffas V. Broussard" [SVBLL@jazz.ucc.uno.edu] Subject: Greek Algebra and Eurocentrism Date: Mon, 20 May 1996 12:34:17 -0600 (CST) Stirling, Thanks for the reply. I agree with much that you say. You asked for clarification on "genetic relationship" and "Eurocentrism." I borrowed the term "genetic relationship" from linguistics. There, a genetic relationship is established between two languages when they are shown to have the same phonetic correspondences according to "sound laws" within a particular language family. This is contrasted with a typological relationship which is based on resemblances between languages due to borrowing and contaminations from contact and other cultural influences. I didn't intend to draw an analogy here between biological evolution and cultural development, but only used the term metonymically in the sense that language is a part of culture. However, that a genetic relationship ( genetic in analogy with linguistics or evolution) as opposed to a relationship dependent on contact and borrowing has been asserted between the two cultures can not be denied. Read any middle or high school history text, browse through any public library, examine the journals. Or, for example, listen to Heidegger, one of the greatest European philosophers of this century, go on and on about the intimate relationship between the German and Greek languages, the only languages suitable for philosophy, a Eurocentric notion indeed. It is this assertion that I questioned. ************ Why Eurocentrism Should Be Included In This Debate ************ In reference to Eurocentrism and Eurocentrics, you wrote on 19 May 1996: I am interested in what they say only in the negative sense. The declaration that some one else is a "eurocentric" seems to me to be primarily a code word for "you are a nazi racist" -implying somehow that the target of the accusation supports the aryan state models. Further in almost every case when I read that some group of people "are unable to uncover their basic assumptions" I find the subtext is "and those basic asusmptions are that their culture is one big conspiracy against people like me". From your post, I know that you would agree that there is a need to tell the true story of mathematics. On 19 May 1996, you wrote : What irks me about teaching of Algebra in America is that while Geometry is taught with reference to names and people, and so is calculus and analytic geometry, Algebra, which was not developed by Europeans in any significant way, one gets simply formulas and proofs. No mention of the long arguments which finally lead to the full acceptance of negative solutions to quadratics or the bionomial theorum. Silence. However, the phenomena of which you speak has a cause, namely, the almost universal belief in the 19th and early 20th century, a belief that is alive and well today, that non-European cultures were incapable of making genuine mathematical and scientific discoveries. This is part of what I am referring to when I speak of Eurocentrism. Nazis did not invent the science of race, or scientific racism, neither did they invent Eurocentrism, which has been a general feature of European civilization since the late 18th century. Much of it was invented by European intellectuals. But, this is part of the story also, which must be told. Since any corrective which seeks to give more accurate and complete presentations of the history of mathematics, will also need to address historiographic issues in the history of mathematics. And it must be told, because my people need to recover from the humiliation and degradation of European slander against their humanity promulgated through European cultural hegemony for at least the last two hundred years. In my reading of European historians of mathematics and science, I have found two Eurocentric features almost always present: 1) the privileging of Greek mathematics over the mathematics of other ancient cultures and 2) the characterization of mathematics in such a way that it becomes a Greek creation. These two features partially constitute the Eurocentrism of which I speak. Moreover, the Eurocentric search for identity through history clearly has a history and we can identify some of its themes: 1) Common values are shared by modern European and ancient Greek civilization. Rationality and scientific method are examples. Differences between the two civilizations are excluded in order to construct an isomorphism between them; 2) by ignoring singularities along the path of European development, a continuous zigzag is drawn from ancient Greece to modern Europe. Selection and combination, metaphor and metonymy are tools of historical writing. Here, selection includes omission. It is evident that cultural beliefs influence selection and combination in historical writing. However, for Eurocentric historians, what seems to be missing is an awareness that the beliefs described above influence what they select and combine in writing histories of science and mathematics and, how in their selection and combination, they reinforce those same beliefs. I offer the following examples of Eurocentric writing. The first two dealing with Indian mathematics and the others with Greek and Egyptian mathematics. Indian Mathematics and Proof Consider the opinions of the following two historians concerning Indian Mathematics. Let's begin with a late opinion from Lloyd (1990)[[1]]. It would appear that before, in, and after the Sulbasutra [the earliest know evidence of mathematics from India], right down to the modern representatives of that tradition, we are dealing with men who tolerate, on ocassion, rough and ready techniques. They are interested in practical results and show no direct concern with proof procedures as such at all. (Lloyd, 1990, p. 104) And from a text found in every university library in the world written by Kline (1972)[[2]]: There is much good procedure and technical facility, but no evidence that they (i.e., the Indians) consider proof at all. They had rules, but apparently no logical scruples. Moreover, no general methods or new viewpoints were arrived at in any area of mathematics. It is fairly certain that the Hindus (i.e., the Indians) did not appreciate the significance of their own contributions. The few good ideas they had, such as separate symbols for the numbers, were introduced causally with no realization that they were valuable innovations. They were not sensitive to mathematical values. (Kline, 1972, p.190) An early Indian Proof: Now consider the following example from the Apastamba Sulvastura (which can be dated anywhere from 1000 B.C to 200 A.D.) The translation is taken from Seidenberg [[3]]. An altar is described in the form of an isosceles trapezium with its eastern base 24 units, its western 30, its width (from M to L) 36. The text says that the area is 972 square units. The priest proceeds to prove the propositions. I have omitted certain phrases in the proof. The abridged proof follows: E F A M D _____************************ | * |* | * | * | * | * |******************************** B L E C W One draws a line from D toward C to the point E which is 12 (padas from the point L). Thereupon one turns the piece cut off (i.e., the triangle DEC) around and carries it to the other side (i.e. to the north). Thus, the vedi obtains the form of a rectangle. In this form (FBED) one computes its area. Is this not a proof? There are many more instances in the Sulvasutras and other Indian works. One can only ask how closely did they bother to examine these works. Of course, the Sulvasutras are religious works and given the predilection on the part of Eurocentric historians to consider myth, ritual and religion as unscientific, they may not have read them closely at all. This predilection is part of their rationalist disposition, a shadow of Greek rationalism. Yet, even, if we allow that they did read these great works, the question arises would they have recognized the proofs as proof. For Kline and Lloyd would have looked for mathematical discussions within a formal deductive system. After all, if they could find no derivations from formally stated axioms in these works, then no "real mathematics" could possibly inhabit these vibrant works. This is precisely the characterization of mathematics that makes it a uniquely Greek creation and excludes non-European mathematics from the mathematical table. The Transmission of Geometry to Greece Most of this is in a previous post, but I will assume you missed it. However, I believe the following account illustrates how European writing and rewriting of the history of science can reflect how one eventually invents Europe and Eurocentric culture. In his classic work on ancient mathematics and astronomy, "Science Awakening" [[4]], published in 1961, B.L. Van Der Waerden began his chapter on Egyptian mathematics by assembling testimonies from Aristotle, Herodotus, and Democritus that praise the mathematical abilities of the Egyptians. However, his aim was to discredit this testimony. He wrote, "We are going to show that Egyptian geometry is not a science in the Greek sense of the word, but merely applied arithmetic.." It might appear that his arguments were based on the extant Egyptian mathematical texts; after all, he used the analytic tools of modern scholarship and followed the tradition of another great european scholar of ancient science, Otto Neugebauer, much of whose work he incorporates. Neugebauer would find little to disagree with in Van Der Waerden's work. However, Van Der Waerden narrowly interpreted the texts, dismissing and arguing away any evidence that might support an "hypothesis concerning a lost Egyptian higher mathematics", and offering explanations of the texts that in the words of Neugebauer are "preferable." "What could the Greeks have learned from the Egyptians?" he asked. Nothing, he concluded. After all, he found nothing in their extant texts and the evidence from Babylonian mathematics supplies a basis for Greek mathematics. So, "we do not need to set up hypotheses concerning a lost Egyptian higher mathematics." In an article published the next year, [[3]], Abraham Seidenberg argued that the very evidence that Van Der Waerden brings forward proves the opposite. According to Seidenberg, from this same evidence, we must conclude that the Egyptians knew that the ratio of the circumference of the circle to its diameter was 4 times the ratio of the area of any circle to the square on its diameter. "And how did they come to such a realization?" Seidenberg asked. "Surely by using their intelligence," he concluded. "If this was done through a geometric analysis--and we see no other way--then this analysis, no matter how crude, shows that Egyptian geometrical knowledge was not merely arithmetical." In "Geometry and Algebra in Ancient Civilizations", published in 1983 [[5]], Van Der Waerden yielded to Seidenberg's arguments: "Modern authors, including myself, have sometimes adopted a skeptical view towards the idea that the mathematical sciences were transmitted from Egypt to Greece....At present I believe this skepticism is not quite justified and that there may be a considerable truth in the statements of Herodotus, Democritus, and Aristotle." However, he didn't retreated entirely from the Eurocentric position. In his own words, "On the other hand, we need not adopt Aristotle's opinion that the mathematical sciences originated in Egypt. It seems much more probable that they originated in Neolithic Europe, and they were subsequently transmitted to China, India, Babylonia, Egypt and Greece." Reasonable arguments do not dampen the Eurocentric desire to be at the origin of things. While Van Der Waerden has been willing to abandon the Greek outpost of European civilization, albeit, for the interior of Europe Major, many Eurocentric scholars continue to resist. As an example in the 1990s of the continued privileging of Greek mathematics over the mathematics of other ancient cultures, we can read Jens Hoyrop discussing scientific (Greek) and subscientific (Babylonia and Egyptian) mathematics, using Aristotle to develop his ideas. At the same time, Hoyrop [[6]] can boldly quote from Aristotle's "Metaphysics" on the origins of science but omit from the same quote the statement: "Thus, the mathematical sciences originated in a neighborhood of Egypt." The story of the European writing and rewrting of the history of science and mathemtics will be told. It is an important part of our history. It will be told and retold. I hope I have clarified some things for you and thanks for reading this far. [[1]] Lloyd, G.E.R. (1990) _Demystifying Mentalities_, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. [[2]] Kline,M. (1972) _Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times_, New York, Oxford University Press. [[3]] Seidenberg, Abraham (1963), "The Ritual Origins of Geometry", _Archive for History of the Exact Sciences_, 1, pp.487-527. [[4]] Van Der Waerden, B.L. (1961), _Science Awakening_, New York, Oxford University Press. [[5]] Van Der Waerden, B.L. (1983),_Geometry and Algebra in Ancient Civilizations_, New York, Springer-Verlag [[6]] Hoyrup, Jens (1994), _In Measure, Number, and Weight_, New York, State University of New York Press. Staffas ------------------ To: uunet!athena-discuss%info.harpercollins.com@uunet.uu.net From: "S.F. Thomas" Subject: Egyptian Science, the Greeks, and Mathematical PROOF Date: Sat, 18 May 1996 17:10:47 +0100 paul manansala wrote: (( cuts )) > > Also, concerning Egyptian math, the Afrocentric > side would be having one difficult time if not > for the discovery of the Rhind, Moscow, Kahun, Berlin > and other papyri, despite the historical evidence > and the colossal engineering works of the Egyptians. So true... I've been lurking here for some time, and thought finally I should weigh in, and lend Paul a hand, not that he needs it, he has been doing a great job here. (Hi Paul, remember me from afojs? Glad to see you again.) First, let me state my credentials and get that out of the way. I have none. I am not an Egyptologist, nor am I a mathematician. But I do have a Ph.D in a mathematical field, and I have spent considerable time thinking about notions of PROOF, and have written a book, _Fuzziness_and_Probability_, which bears (tangentially to be sure) on the subject. As to any bias I might bring to the subject, let me identify myself as of the African diaspora, born and raised in the Caribbean, schooled in the Western tradition. My bias is therefore with the Afrocentrists, for having read Diop, James, Bernal and others, it has become clear to me that more than a threshold showing has been made that Western scholarship has been Eurocentric at the expense of truth. Malcolm X said, "we have been hoodwinked, we have been brainwashed, and we have been bamboozled," (or something such) in referring to the lies that have been taught us in the history books about black people and their origins. Bernal, more scholarly, says that the Ancient Model was supplanted in the 18th and 19th centuries by the Aryan Model, a milder way of saying the same thing, while adverting to the racist motives that lay beneath the historical distortions that constitute the received (Eurocentric) history to this day. Diop puts the matter more plainly, as does James. James spoke of a "stolen legacy", while Diop has accused the ancient Greeks of nothing less than plagiarism. That is a serious charge, and Diop succeeds, brilliantly in my opinion, in making a prima facie case in support of the charge. I am not an Egyptologist, as I said, therefore I cannot offer an independent opinion of the factual claims on which his argument rests. But the charge appears compelling. For those who have not read it, I commend his _Civilisation_or_Barbarism_, specifically the discussion in Chapter 16, "Africa's Contribution: Sciences". Here is the charge of plagiarism: First as to Archimedes: Now, a sphere inscribed in a right cylinder of a height equal to the diameter of the sphere is the same figure that Archimedes chose as his epitaph, considering that this is his best discovery (fig. 41). Thus, Archimedes did not even have the excuse of an honest scholar who would rediscover an established theorem, without knowing that it had been discovered two thousand years before him by his Egyptian predecessors [from papyrus evidence previously elaborated in the chapter]. The other "borrowings" in which he indulged himself during and after his trip to Egypt, without ever citing the sources of his inspiration, show clearly that he was perfectly conscious of his sin, and that thereby he was being faithful to a Greek tradition of plagiarism that went back to Thales, Pythagoras, Plato, Eudoxus, Oenopides, Aristotle, etc., which the testimonies of Herodotus and Diodorus of Sicily reveal to us in part... The epitaph of Archimedes, rediscovered by Cicero at Syracuse, proves that this is not a myth propagated by tradition. Second as to Thales: The theorem attributed to Thales is illustrated by the figure of problem 53 of the Rhind Papyrus, written thirteen hundred years before the birth of Thales... The anecdote claiming that Thales discovered "his" theorem by making the end of the shadow cast by a stick, planted vertically, meet exactly the end of the shadow cast by the Great Pyramid, in order to have a figure materialize identically to that of problem 53, would only prove that Thales actually spent time in Egypt, that he was truly a pupil of Egyptian priests and that he could not be the inventor of the theorem attributed to him. Third as to Pythagoras: Herodotus calls Pythagoras a simple plagiarist of the Egyptians; Jamblichus, biographer of Pythagoras, writes that all the theorems of lines (geometry) come from Egypt... An Egyptian priest told Diodorus of Sicily that all the so-called discoveries that made Greek scholars famous were things that had been taught to them in Egypt and which they called their own, once they went back to their country... Fourth as to Plato: Plato, in the Phaedrus, has Socrates say that he learned that the god Thoth was the inventor of arithmetic, calculus, geometry, and astronomy (Phaedrus, 274 C)... Fifth as to Aristotle and Democritus: Aristotle... acknowledges the essentially theoretical and speculative character of the Egyptian science and tries to explain its emergence not by land surveying, but by the fact that the Egyptian priests were free from material preoccupations and had all the time necessary to deepen theoretical thought. According to Herodotus, the Egyptians are the exclusive inventors of geometry, which they taught to the Greeks. Democritus boasted that he equalled the Egyptians in geometry. And Diop's conclusion: Therefore, no trace is found anywhere, in the texts of antiquity, of a so-called duality of theoretical Greek science, as opposed to Egyptian empiricism... The idea of an empirical Egyptian science is an invention of modern ideologues, those same ones who are looking for ways to erase from the memory of humanity the influence of Negro Egypt on Greece. In the interest of brevity, I have of course left out much detail, but I believe Diop has succeeded in making the threshold showing of deliberate plagiarism, as opposed to innocent borrowing, or independent rediscovery of previously known results. If that is in fact the historical truth, then the fact of plagiarism renders moot the question of Greek theory vs. Egyptian empiricism, for it will never be known where the Egyptian contribution ends, and the Greek begins. Still, though, it is contended by some on the list that what the papyri do not show is mathematical PROOF, in the sense that has come down to us in, for example, Euclid's "Elements". If one chooses to argue *only* from the surviving papyri, there may be a point to this contention. But one would then have to ignore the totality of the evidence, including the assertions attributed to Herodotus and Diodorus, not to mention Plato and Aristotle. In any case, even if argument is confined to the evidence solely of the surviving papyri, the point would still be a weak one, given the nature of mathematical PROOF itself, which I now address. The axiomatic method is indeed very powerful. That is what mathematical PROOF ultimately boils down to: stating premises which are hopefully self-evident and therefore not themselves requiring of PROOF, then applying syllogistic reasoning based on the premises to obtain the result (theorem) that is sought. But it is a mistake to suppose that PROOF has not been established unless a minimal set of axioms has first been laid down. Theorems in one system may be axioms in another, and vice versa, and the choice is essentially arbitrary. Therefore, if the Egyptians had a result, as evidenced by the algorithms in the papyri applying those results, it seems a fair inference that they had found some way beforehand to establish the result then applied. That their axiomatization has not survived is not proof that there was not one; rather, the converse seems more reasonable, namely that if they could implement a result, they must have got to that point by some syllogistic reasoning process. *How* they got there may not be known, but axiomatizations are essentially arbitrary, sometimes explicit, sometimes only implicit, but if there is a *result*, some axiomatization, whether efficient or otherwise, minimal or otherwise, systematic or otherwise, must be assumed to have preceded the result. We sometimes forget that only a very meager theory of meaning is required to apply the axiomatic method. Rules of logical deduction have been elaborated which follow entirely from logical form, for example: All rich men are happy (Premise 1) John is rich (Premise 2) Therefore, John is happy (Conclusion) Leave aside the factual truth or otherwise of the premises, and leave aside the semantic uncertainty associated with the fuzzy terms "rich" and "happy", the conclusion follows as a matter of form. The two premises entail, logically, the conclusion. Raised to perfect abstraction, we have the tautological rule known as modus ponendo ponens, under which, from propositions A, and A->B, we may reliably infer B, which in the standard logic notation emerges as [A & (A->B) ] -> B where A and B may remain uninterpreted until we have a special case such as [rich & rich->happy ] -> happy which may help us "prove" that, say, O. J. Simpson is a happy man. Of course, in any particular case, we haven't proved anything except that IF we assume certain premises, THEN certain conclusions would be semantically consistent with those premises. Mathematical proof is of the same sort. It is ultimately empty, because it cannot by itself establish for us the premises which we hope correspond in some way with reality. Therefore, I am far more impressed with a concrete result, eg. the pyramids, than I am with some mathematical proof. When in addition the papyri clearly indicate knowledge of various *formulae* (with the full generality implicit in that word) clearly used in pyramid building -- areas, volumes, trigonometric relations, geometric series, arithmetic series, etc. -- I find it absurd to question whether the builders understood abstract mathematical PROOF. Parenthetically, much of modern mathematics (the Hilbert program) has been wasted attempting to make of it a robotic exercise in uninterpreted symbol manipulation, except, perhaps, very minimally, at the axiomatic outset. It is perhaps not surprising the result of Godel that not all theorems (of arithmetic) are decidable within such a framework. Some results would appear to require a reversion to a fuller theory of meaning, where deduction derives from semantic *content* rather than merely semantic *form*. (Which, btw, is where fuzziness comes in, so far as my book is concerned, for fuzzy sets can be bearers or explicators of semantic content, from which rules of deduction based on content rather than merely of form, may be derived.) It is the old limitation of traditional logic: one cannot use modus ponendo ponens or other rules of logical form to deduce from the description "bachelor" that one is an "unmarried man". The logical robot would have to be programmed some other way. But man is not robot. Syllogistic reasoning, which is the chief stock-in-trade, though not the only one, of mathematical science, is in any case not the supreme intellectual accomplishment of which we humans are capable. Far from it. And there is evidence that the Egyptians put it fairly low in the totem pole of human accomplishment. They saw man as being a spiritual being, with a spirit having seven divisions, in each of which the consciousness performed different types of functions, as follows: 1 - Ba, the ability to experience omnipresence based on the existence of the universal spirit 2 - Khu, ability to intuit the truth of a logical premise, the oracular faculty of prophets 3 - Shekem, ability to affect nature through the use of spiritual power 4 - Ab, + the ability to see the interdependence between all things, to love + the ability to analyze, to see the abstract difference between things + the ability to think circumspectly, ie. to coordinate the activity of all the faculties of the spirit, to reason. 5 - Sahu, + imagination and congregative thinking-- aesthetics __________________________________________ | + syllogistic, logical and segregative | | thinking | ------------------------------------------ + memory and imitative faculty, learning 6 - Khaibit, the animal soul, emotions, sense perception, the sensual, physical movement 7 - Khab, the physical body which gives us the illusion that we are separate beings I do not claim to know what all of this means (see "An Afrocentric Guide to a Spiritual Union", by Ra Un Nefer Amen for further elaboration) but if we accept the essential claim that this hierarchical structuring of the spirit is due to the ancients, then it reveals a clear understanding of syllogistic reasoning which is the foundation of the axiomatic method attributed to the Greeks. It also puts it rather low in the totem pole of human activity. He who can do more can also do less, as Diop is fond of saying. Therefore, the axiomatic method of syllogistic reasoning appears to fall well within the wisdom systems developed by the Egyptians, and to suggest that they fell short in that area therefore seems unreasonable. It also suggests that we of the 20th century who fall far short of levels 1, 2 and 3 above in accomplishment, may not yet have the ability to appreciate fully the achievements of the ancients. Finally, Diop tells us that the earliest date in history known with certainty is 4236 BC, because there is evidence that the Egyptians developed at that time the sidereal calendar, a fact which suggests rather more than empirical knowledge on their part: They invented the 365-day year, breaking it down as follows: 12 months of 30 days = 360 days, plus the 5 intercalated days .... The Egyptians knew that this calendar year was too short, that it was lacking a quarter of a day in order for it to correspond to a complete sidereal revolution... [In] 4236 BC they invented a second astronomical calendar founded precisely on this time lag ... in the 365-day calendar as compared to the sidereal, or astronomical, calendar. The time lag thus accumulated at the end of four years is equal to one day. Instead of adding 1 day every 4 years and thus instituting a leap year, the Egyptians preferred the masterful solution that consists of following this time lag for 1,460 years... the Egyptians preferred to "rectify" every 1,460 years instead of every 4 years; he who can do more can also do less, therefore contrary to popular opinion, they knew the leap year very well. But what is still more amazing is that the Egyptians had equally (observed?) calculated that this period of 1,460 years of the sidereal calendar is the lapse of time that separates two helical risings of Sirius, the most brilliant fixed star in the heavens located in the constellation Canis Major... Thus, the heliacal rising of Sirius, which takes place every 1,460 years, coinciding with the first day of the year in both calendars, is the absolute chronological reference point that is the basis of the Egyptian astronomical calendar. One gets lost in conjectures in order to figure out *how* the Egyptians were able to arrive at such a result from protohistory, because it is known with certainty that the sidereal calendar was in use from 4236 BC onward. Supposing that a celestial phenomenon as fleeting as a heliacal rising of Sirius had accidentally caught the attention of the Egyptians from the fourth millenium onward, how could they have guessed at, and verified, within a few minutes, its rigorous periodicity, in a time span of 1,460 years, and thus invented a calendar on this basis? Did they arrive at this result through empirical or theoretical means? Assuredly, the disparagers of Egyptian civilization have their work cut out for them! Frankly, I see no other conclusion but that the Egyptians had more than empirical mathematical results at their disposal if they established the sidereal calendar. If you add the tangible evidence of the pyramids, it seems inconceivable to me that they had not mastered both geometry and trigonometry in their full abstraction. If in addition, they established the heliacal risings of Sirius to its 1,460-year periodicity, either they also mastered the equivalent of calculus and Newtonian mechanics, or in the alternative, the part of their civilization lost in proto- history must extend back at least 3,000 years prior to 4236 BC for them to have been able to record the observations necessary to establish the empirical basis for the sidereal calendar. Or both. The latter is consistent with recent theories (West and others) suggesting that the age of the Sphinx is much greater than supposed by Egyptologists, and may have been built/carved in about 10,000 BC to herald the rising of the astrological age of Leo. That in itself would require knowledge of a periodicity of even higher order. The imagination *is* transfixed. I won't even go into the Dogon people of West Africa, and their intimate knowledge of the orbit of Sirius B, the invisible (to the naked eye) companion star to Sirius, and what their connections might be to ancient Egypt. In the light of what the Egyptians for a fact were known to have accomplished (the pyramids, and the sidereal calendar), the question whether the Egyptians invented mathematical PROOF seems tangential and picayune. They knew the required theorems (arithmetic, algebraic, geometric, and trigonometric). If arrived at by mathematical intuition alone, this would be even more remarkable than if arrived at by the imperfect axiomatic method to which we are heirs today, and for which we credit the Greeks. I can think of an analogy. Suppose the world were destroyed (nuclear war, asteroid collision, or whatever), and no books or libraries remained to show what mankind of the 20th century had accomplished. Yet some future sojourners on earth were able to see signs of our being here, and all that was left were some film clip showing the accomplishment of men landing on the moon. Would it be doubted that those people of the 20th century had to have mastered the mathematics necessary to have pulled off the accomplishment? In its full theoretical abstraction? Yes, Paul, you are right. But for the few papyri that survived the destruction of the invader, the ancient accounts of Herodotus and Diodorus, and fortuitous pieces of evidence such as the inscription on Archimedes tomb, the Egyptian claim to what has popularly, and it would appear wrongly, been attributed to the Greeks would be lost to us. > Paul Kekai Manansala Regards, S. F. Thomas -----------------
Ta_Seti, a premier online African-centered discussion group!
Report any problems to Paul Kekai Manansala at
Sponsored by AsiaPacificUniverse.com
Ta_Seti, a premier online African-centered discussion group!